Full text of ' PENGUIN CLASSICS HILDEGARD OF BINGEN: SELECTED WRITINGS HILDEGARD OF BINGEN was born into a noble family in Bermersheim in 1098. At the age of eight her family gave her into the care of a religious noblewoman, Jutta of Spanheim, who took Hildegard with her to become a recluse at the Disibodenberg monastery. Some time between 1112 and 1115, when the monastery became a convent, Hildegard took religious vows.
Hildegard von Bingen's Physica has 125 ratings and 6 reviews. Michael said: Looking at this book, it would seem that Hildegard of Bingen (Germany) was th. Hildegard Bingen Scivias Pdf Merge Online. There are some special events throughout the year on the church calendar, including Easter, Christmas and also services such as Remembrance Day. All of these events have varying demands for music, and many are associated with their own traditional and popular pieces of music. The best-known writing of Hildegard of Bingen is a trilogy (1141–52) including Scivias, Liber Vitae Meritorum, (Book of the Life of Merits), and Liber Divinorum Operum (Book of the Divine Works). These include records of her visions—many are apocalyptic—and her explanations of scripture and salvation history.
After Jutta’s death in 1136, Hildegard was elected abbess at Disibodenberg. At this time she started to write about the visions she had been experiencing. Her first work, Scivias, appeared with Papal approval in 1151, just after she had established her own religious community at Rupertsberg, near Bingen. Her collection of religious songs, the Symphonia, appeared in 1158. She then produced a number of other works, including The Book of Life’s Merits (c.
1163), The Book of Divine Works (c. 113), lives of local saints, and various musical, scientific and medical works. She also invented a private language, which formed the basis of two short works, The Unknown Language and The Unknown Alphabet (both completed by 1158). Hildegard was by this time regarded as a mystic and prophetess, and she came to be known as the ‘Sibyl of the Rhine’. In about 1158 she undertook the first of her preaching tours throughout Germany, a very unusual venture for a medieval abbess. This was followed by three further tours in 1160, 1161-3 and 1170-71. She founded a second monastery at Eibingen in 1165.
Hildegard died in 1179. She was celebrated as a saint in the Rhineland and in the fifteenth century her feast day was established as 17 September.
MARK ATHERTON studied modern languages at Oxford. He trained as a teacher at Bangor and in medieval studies at York, where he completed a doctorate on the linguist and philologist Henry Sweet. He has taught English language, literature and translation at universities in Cologne and Brussels, and researched and published mainly on early medieval literature.
After a period as research associate in Anglo-Saxon studies at the University of Manchester, he is now fellow of the Centre for the Study of Christianity and Culture, Regent’s Park College, Oxford. Hildegard of Bingen SELECTED WRITINGS Translated with an introduction and notes by MARK ATHERTON PENGUIN BOOKS CONTENTS INTRODUCTION I LIFE AND CAREER II HILDEGARD IN HER TIME III HILDEGARD’S WRITINGS FURTHER READING SELECT DISCOGRAPHY CHRONOLOGY TRANSLATOR’S NOTE KNOW THE WAYS 1.
Letter to Bernard of Clairvaux 2. The Action of the Will (from Scivias) 3.
Redemption (from Scivias) 4. Letter to Odo of Soissons 5.
The Trinity (from Scivias) 6. Letter to Pope Eugenius III STRUGGLES FOR INDEPENDENCE 7.
Songs for Saint Disibod 8. Letter to Hartwig of Bremen 9.
Song for Saint Ursula 10. The Trials of the Soul (from Scivias) 11. Songs for Saint Rupert 12. The Departure of Richardis of Stade 13. The First Version of The Play of the Virtues (from Scivias) THE SIBYL OF THE RHINE 14. Three Political Letters 15.
Songs for the Dedication of a Church 16. Teachings on the Church (from Scivias) 17. Letter to Elisabeth of Schonau 18. Gertrud of Stahleck 19.
Letter to the Abbess of Bamberg IN PRAISE OF CREATION 20. The Cosmic Egg (from Scivias) 21. The Cosmos (from Causes and Cures) 22. Gemstones (from Physica) 23. Songs from Symphonia 24. Two Christmas Homilies ALLEGORIES OF JUSTICE AND LOVE 25. The Iron Mountain (from Scivias) 26.
The Man Looking East and South (from The Book of Life’s Merits) 27. The Seven Vices and Virtues (from The Book of Life’s Merits) 28. The Voice from Heaven (from The Book of Life’s Merits) 29. The Unknown Language 30. Allegorical Letters 31. A Vision of Love (from The Book of Divine Works) HILDEGARD’S LIFE AND INFLUENCE 32. Queries and Requests: Selected Letters to Hildegard 33.
From The Life of Hildegard, Book 2, by Theoderich of Echternach 34. Gebeno of Eberbach: The Pentachronon 35. From the Canonization Protocol NOTES GLOSSARY INTRODUCTION I. LIFE AND CAREER l. The making of a writer In 1146, an unknown and unpublished author, abbess of a small convent of nuns attached to the larger monastery of Disibodenberg in the Rhineland, sent a letter to the great churchman of her day, Bernard of Clairvaux. In her opening words, she emphasized Bernard’s fame and her own unworthiness, before moving to her reason for writing. Despite her lack of education, the writer of the letter claimed she was filled with sophisticated and far-reaching theological visions and interpretations of the Bible.
At the same time she also revealed that she was composing elaborate songs and music for use in church, again without having had any specific training. But - worried about pride and presumption - she was plagued with afflictions and doubts. Should she, a mere nun and uneducated woman, continue in such potentially reckless and inappropriate activities? The concluding request of her letter is couched in language and rhetoric the like of which Bernard had almost certainly never seen or heard before.
Hildegard appeals to him in a series of injunctions, some conventional, others highly original. She entreats him not only ‘by the brightness of the Father, by his wonderful Word’, a familiar idea, but also ‘by the sacred sound through which all creation resounds’, a more unusual concept; and perhaps even more startling, ‘by the Word from which all the world was created, by the height of the Father who through the sweet power of green vigour sent the Word to the Virgin’s womb where it took on flesh like the honey in the honeycomb’.
What does she mean by some of these unusual ideas? The ‘sacred sound’ implies an idea of music as the essential fabric of the cosmos. There is a whole world of ideas behind this one phrase. The expression ‘green vigour’, or viriditas in the Latin of the original text, is similarly rich in connotations. For Hildegard, ‘greenness’ means the force which gives life to the body and renewal in nature; in a religious sense it signifies both the power of the Spirit at work in the world and the moral force that gives life and fruitfulness to human actions. With hindsight, we can see the significance of such metaphors and concepts; they are the first expressions in writing of a new religious thinker who already at the time of writing has her own theology. Behind the final phrases of the letter to Bernard we detect a musician with her own philosophy of music, and an artist who - though no classical stylist - was a maker of fresh and startling images and ideas.
Moreover, all this was expressed in a rough, unpolished Latin which Hildegard had acquired without formal study while singing the psalms and prayers of the monastic services in the daily life of her convent. Bernard was evidently impressed, for his short reply was positive. Which is somewhat surprising, given that he was a churchman of the twelfth century, a period in which anything new and strange in religion was probed carefully for heresy. And Bernard was no liberal in such matters: he had secured the prohibition of the teachings of the great Paris philosopher Peter Abelard and his supporter Arnold of Brescia, and at the time of Hildegard’s letter he was also agitating (unsuccessfully in this case) for the condemnation of the doctrines of Gilbert of Poitiers, a theologian who had made some unorthodox statements on the unity of the godhead.
But at the Synod of Trier in the winter of 1147- 8, Hildegard’s work in progress (possibly some sections of part II of her Scivias ) was read out with interest by Pope Eugenius III and others. Bernard spoke in her favour, and papal approval was given for its publication. Within a few years, Hildegard of Bingen had become a religious, moral and political adviser to half of Europe, as her voluminous correspondence shows. Credited with prophetic insights, the ‘Sibyl of the Rhine’ was frequently consulted, and on the basis of her authority as a prophet, undertook what for a woman was almost unheard of: four preaching tours through the heartlands of the German Empire. She began her preaching in 1158, at the age of sixty, and the first tour took her along the Main, stopping at Mainz, Wertheim, Wurzburg, Kitzingen, Ebrach and Bamberg, preaching in churches and cathedrals and visiting abbeys and monasteries.
A further three tours followed. In 1160, she preached publicly in Trier, attacked the lax clergy for not ‘blowing the trumpet of God’s justice’, then proceeded along the River Mosel to Metz. Between 1161 and 1163 she followed the Rhine northwards to Werden on the Ruhr, stopping at Cologne, where she preached on the dangers of the Cathar movement (on which more below). Finally, from 1170 to 1171, she was in Swabia. Here, as a letter to Werner of Kirchheim reveals, she preached to a community of priests on the topic of the Church, which she saw as a mystical female figure towering to the heavens (like Lady Philosophy in Boethius’s Consolation of Philosophy ) but whose white robe was torn and dishevelled.
1 In true Gregorian reformist manner, she called for the clerics to end their neglect of the Church, to lead celibate lives and to stop chasing after preferments. There are no descriptions of these journeys other than the letters in which Hildegard sent copies of her sermons to the communities she had visited, but the requests reveal how well she was received. Although her decision to undertake such tours was clearly justified by their reception, they were highly irregular. The enormity of the step she took is perhaps appreciated when it is recalled that Benedictine nuns could not leave their cloister without special permission, and only priests were allowed to preach. But Hildegard had the authority of her vocation and a strength of character which brooked almost no opposition. Rooting her ideas in what she called her ‘vision’, a religious experience of the ‘living light’, she set herself the task of writing an encyclopedic survey of theological knowledge. Her basic method was to present a particular ‘vision’ with all its imagery and detail in a coherent picture, both as a text and, in some manuscripts, as an illustration.
Shown in this way the picture would take on a life of its own, almost like a myth, but remain at the same time something mysterious, ‘a mystical vision’ as she called it, demanding a key to its meaning. This she would then set out to give, explaining the content of the picture she had created and making it relevant to her contemporary audience. The dozens of visions were subsequently arranged into a series of three interconnected books: Scivias, or Know the Ways (completed in 1151), The Book of Life’s Merits (1163), and The Book of Divine Works (1173). The trilogy became her life’s work: a body of writing based on ‘visions’ but covering a wide area of teaching: from knowledge about the cosmos, explanations of the meaning of the Trinity and other religious ideas to interpretations of passages in the Bible, ethical and social problems, and pastoral care and medicine. Particularly in the first half of her career, Hildegard composed choral music for the liturgy, collecting the various pieces in her work the Symphony of the Harmony of Celestial Revelations (1158). It is these songs, which have survived as text with neums (medieval musical notation) and are now recorded in a number of versions, that have brought renewed fame to Hildegard in the present day.
Several additional works should be noted. Hildegard wrote ‘non-visionary’ prose, in particular two treatises on medicine and the natural world known as Causes and Cures and Physica, both completed by 1158. As with the songs, great attention has recently been given to these writings after a long neglect. In particular, her emphasis on wholeness, balance and diet has given them renewed currency among today’s readership. During the same period of activity, as the preface to her Book of Life’s Merits reveals, she also compiled her ‘replies and admonitions’, i.e. The first collected edition of her letters, as well as various minor writings: a commentary on the Gospels, an explanation of the Athanasian Creed and a commentary on the Benedictine Rule for Monasteries.
There later followed the Life of St Disibod, the Life of St Rupert and the Solutions to Thirty-Eight Questions. Finally, mention should be made of two works (composed 1151-8) in which Hildegard revealed a fascination with language and the invention of private languages: The Unknown Language and The Unknown Alphabet. In the decade after her death in 1179, most of her large corpus of writings was gathered together and edited in one volume at the Rupertsberg, the monastery she herself had founded in about 1150; the result is the so-called ‘giant’ book or codex, usually referred to by its German title, the Riesenkodex. Sketch of Hildegard’s life Hildegard’s inner life was frequently turbulent, but outwardly the routine of the convent remained a highly ordered, regular round of singing the monastic ‘offices’, or services, at set times throughout the day as prescribed in the Benedictine Rule for Monasteries. It should be remembered that one of Hildegard’s main purposes in composing music was to supplement the daily round with short pieces - antiphons and responsories - which could be included at suitable points in the course of the liturgy of the offices. Given the regularity of her everyday life, the main external events of her biography can be quickly told.
For the first forty-two years of her life Hildegard led a sheltered existence, much of it within the walls of a monastery. Born at Bermersheim in 1098 into a well-established noble family, she was given to the monastic life as a young child; according to Guibert’s Life of Hildegard, her parents felt a need to offer their tenth and youngest child as a ‘tithe’, to be presented to the Church in dedication. In Hildegard’s case the dedication as ‘oblate’ took place with her full agreement, although, as we shall see, she objected strongly to the practice of dedicating oblates to monasteries without their consent. According to Theoderich’s Life of Hildegard, Hildegard was aged eight at the time, and she was put into the care of a pious noblewoman called Jutta of Spanheim, presumably at her household in nearby Spanheim itself. Rather than immediately entering an anchorage (as told in the now traditional account based on Theoderich’s Life ) it now seems likely that she remained at Spanheim for a number of years while Jutta looked for a suitable convent. The Annals of Disibodenberg report that on 29 June 1108 the foundation stone of the newly rebuilt monastery of Disibodenberg was laid by its abbot, Burchard.
For reasons not recorded, Jutta decided on this as the site of her retreat from the world. Accordingly, as details in the anonymous Life of Jutta indicate, Jutta became a recluse attached to the monastery in 1112, taking Hildegard and another young dedicatee with her.
The anchorage soon became a convent at what was in effect a double monastery (with two separate houses on the same site for monks and nuns). Subsequently, at some point in the next four years, Hildegard spoke her vows and assumed the veil of a nun.
The following twenty years passed without notice, but when Jutta died in 1136, the nuns chose Hildegard as her successor. Having achieved a secure position, Hildegard felt able to tell selected friends about her visionary experiences and creative abilities. Encouraged by her friend the monk Volmar, schoolmaster of the monastery, she began in 1141 to put her ‘vision’ into writing. Work continued until the eventful synod of 1147-8, when, prompted by Kuno, the abbot of Disibodenberg, and supported by Heinrich, the archbishop in the local diocese of Mainz, she presented it for papal approval. The result of this synod has already been told, and from this point on Hildegard’s life was transformed as she assumed the active role of author, preacher, counsellor and (to use a modern term) a form of therapist. More of the details of this new role will emerge as we consider her letters, her trilogy and other individual works. But apart from the preaching journeys, and the foundation of Eibingen in 1165, her active career is marked by drastic events only at its beginning and end.
Soon after the Synod of Trier, her outer circumstances changed. In about 1150, as she was completing Scivias, she abandoned the monks at Disibodenberg and set up her own foundation at Rupertsberg. At first, resources were limited for the abbess and her small band of twenty or so nuns, and the situation was exacerbated by active opposition to the move on the part of Abbot Kuno of Disibodenberg.
Meanwhile, in the face of the hardships, various nuns left the Rupertsberg for elsewhere. These included the nun Adelheid, who became abbess of Gandersheim, and Hildegard’s close friend Richardis of Stade, who moved to Bassum; in both cases there seem to have been family and political connections involved in the appointments. The departure of Richardis was a bitter disappointment for Hildegard, which is recorded graphically in one of her letters translated below. To solve the financial situation of the convent, Hildegard made a surprise visit to Kuno and secured an agreement for the support of the nuns (the money was owed to them as revenue from lands given to the monastery by their wealthy relatives).
Before the deal was ratified, however, Kuno died in 1155, and the dispute was renewed under his successor, Abbot Helenger, who tried to secure the return to Disibodenberg of the invaluable Volmar, who was still supporting Hildegard in her writing work. Eventually, by appeals to the diocese, in particular to Arnold, Archbishop of Mainz, two charters were obtained in 1158 which secured the nuns’ property and arranged for pastoral and priestly visits from Disibodenberg to Rupertsberg. At the end of her life, the daily routines of the convent and, what was worse, the very achievements of Hildegard’s career were threatened by wholly unexpected circumstances. A young nobleman, who had been excommunicated, died after reconciling himself with the Church and receiving the sacraments from a priest. He was buried in the convent cemetery. Though everything had proceeded correctly, this event had repercussions. Alleging that he had still been excommunicant at the time of his death, the prelates of the diocese of Mainz ordered his body to be removed.
Hildegard refused to do this. The prelates accordingly placed an interdict over the Rupertsberg, forbidding the nuns to take part in communion or to sing the liturgy, and they were allowed to say their prayers and readings only in muffled tones. In a medieval Christian context, and particularly in the situation of a convent, where the mass, the psalms and the offices were the very lifeblood of their existence, the nuns were devastated, or, in their own words, ‘afflicted with much bitterness’ and ‘oppressed by a great sadness.’ Hildegard herself, who set so much store by music as ‘the sacred sound through which all creation resounds’, was beside herself. A letter written during this dispute is particularly interesting, for here Hildegard was compelled to put her views on music into writing in order to appeal for a lifting of the ban on the singing of the liturgy. After various visits and appeals, in which - as the letters and biography reveal - the local rivalries between the diocese of Mainz and that of Cologne also played a role, the interdict was finally lifted. For the last few months of her life Hildegard’s activities returned to the normal Benedictine routine of prayer and praise to which her vocation had called her.
HILDEGARD IN HER TIME i. The Cistercians The period in which Hildegard lived was a time of great renewal, often referred to as the Twelfth-Century Renaissance.
2 One driving force was the new monastic order of the Cistercians, an offshoot of the Benedictine Order, who called for a return to the basics of the Benedictine Rule, including simplicity of worship (in contrast to the elaborate rituals of the established Cluniac monasteries), and manual labour; they also emphasized the role of meditation and reading.3 The most important personality of Cistercian monasticism was clearly Bernard of Clairvaux, who taught the future Pope Eugenius III. Bernard’s writings, mostly spiritual and contemplative, were extremely influential in the period, and his political influence was immense. Here, to give a brief example, is an admonition from his On Consideration, a series of reflections on government which he addressed to Pope Eugenius III: See where your accursed occupations are bound to drag you if you carry on as you have begun, that is to say, giving yourself wholly to them and saving nothing of yourself for you.
You are wasting time and, if I may play Jethro to your Moses, you, like him, are wearing yourself out in foolish labour over things which are nothing but an affliction of spirit, the dissipation of your mental energies and an expense of grace. And what does it yield you in the end but cobwebs?4 On a humorous note, Bernard could also write a satirical view of a wealthy Cluniac abbot travelling round the country in a grand style with all his rich household goods and ‘sixty or more horses in his train’.
Charles Singer’s retrospective diagnosis of Hildegard of Bingen as a migraine sufferer, first made in 1913, has become commonly accepted. This article uses Hildegard as a case study to shift our focus from a polarised debate about the merits or otherwise of retrospective diagnosis, to examine instead what happens when diagnoses take on lives of their own. It argues that simply championing or rejecting retrospective diagnosis is not enough; that we need instead to appreciate how, at the moment of creation, a diagnosis reflects the significance of particular medical signs and theories in historical context and how, when and why such diagnoses can come to do meaningful work when subsequently mobilised as scientific ‘fact’.
This article first traces the emergence of a new formulation of migraine in the nineteenth century, then shows how this context enabled Singer to retrospectively diagnose Hildegard’s migraine and finally examines some of the ways in which this idea has gained popular and academic currency in the second half of the twentieth century. The case of Hildegard’s migraine reminds us of the need to historicise scientific evidence just as rigorously as we historicise our other material and it exposes the cumulative methodological problems that can occur when historians use science, and scientists use history on a casual basis. 1. Introduction In 1913, a young scientist and historian named Charles Singer was in Germany researching precursors to modern theories of contagion. In Wiesbaden, he consulted the twelfth-century illuminated Scivias manuscript (c.1165) which described 26 religious visions experienced by the celebrated St Rupertsberg abbess, Hildegard of Bingen (1098–1179). In the stars, shimmering points of light and crenellated figures of some of the 35 illuminations in Scivias, Singer thought that he recognised depictions of ‘scintillating scotoma’.
Noting that Hildegard had admitted to long periods of illness, Singer diagnosed a functional nervous disorder, specifically migraine. Nearly a century later, medical ideas about migraine have changed a great deal. Nevertheless, Singer’s retrospective diagnosis of Hildegard’s migraine has persisted, gaining popularity in the late twentieth century as the abbess’ reputation has grown. Hildegard’s migraine has appeared in some significant places, including Oliver Sacks’ Migraine (1970), scholarly publications in medieval history and a pharmaceutical marketing campaign. More recently, on the internet, contributors to blogs and websites have freely proposed Hildegard as a ‘patron saint’ of migraine and migraineurs. There is a large scholarly output in English, German and French by historians specialising in Hildegardian studies. This grapples (among other themes) with whether Hildegard suffered from migraine, whether she was the designer of the Scivias illuminations, and whether she was the author of the medical text Causae et Curae.
I should make it clear from the outset that while I am not attempting to make new claims about Hildegard’s own experiences of illness or the authenticity of the works that have been attributed to her oeuvre, this literature has played an important part in informing this piece; each of these three questions has their own independent scholarly history, but they converged in Singer’s argument. Instead, I am interested here in tracing a twentieth-century story about how the creation of new medical understandings of migraine provided Charles Singer with evidence to diagnose Hildegard’s migraine and how, subsequently, this diagnosis has been used in different ways to help authenticate particular arguments about illness in the past and present. In doing so, I do not aim to reject retrospective diagnosis tout court. Much of the extant debate on retrospective diagnosis has revolved around the motives of those making the diagnosis, or has traced how historical figures have attracted competing diagnoses as medical knowledge has changed. Here, I wish to use Hildegard as a case study that shifts our focus from a polarised debate about the merits or otherwise of retrospective diagnosis as an act, and to examine instead what happens when diagnoses take on lives of their own. Simply championing or rejecting retrospective diagnosis is not enough.
I argue that we need instead to appreciate not only how, at the moment of creation, a diagnosis reflects the significance of particular medical signs and theories in any given historical context but also how, when and why such diagnoses can come to do subsequent meaningful work when mobilised as scientific ‘fact’. The first section of this article charts a pre-history to Singer’s diagnosis, in the emergence of a new dominant medical formulation of migraine in the nineteenth century, which emphasised migraine as a disorder associated with aura, vision and science. The second section examines how Singer used this formulation to identify Hildegard’s migraine, and how in turn this advanced his own arguments about the medieval development of science. Third, I look at how Hildegard’s migraine took on new life in the second half of the twentieth century in Oliver Sacks’ incorporation of Singer’s ideas and Hildegard’s imagery in his famous study Migraine, and the endeavours of historians to assert the authenticity of Hildegard’s manuscripts, using the migraine diagnosis as evidence.
In each case, I show how Hildegard’s migraine has proved attractive not because of its ‘truth’, but because it served to advance a particular argument or position. In the final section, I demonstrate the methodological problems that can result from the decontextualisation and accumulation over time of what Felicity Callard has termed ‘interdisciplinary borrowings’. The case of Hildegard’s migraine reminds us of the need to historicise scientific evidence just as rigorously as we historicise our images and texts. 2. Retrospective Diagnosis The issue of retrospective diagnosis has long exercised historians of medicine.
Do histories that mine the past for symptoms or traces corresponding to current medical knowledge tell us anything about medical history? Or should we write histories that respect and contextualise historical knowledge on its own terms? This approach accepts, in Andrew Cunningham’s words, that ‘you die of what your doctor says you die of’, however outdated these contemporary pronouncements might now seem to our modern gaze. While practitioners of retrospective diagnosis consider the employment of modern biomedical categories as a perfectly valid way to talk about disease in the past, others have criticised the practice’s tendency to reduce the lives of individuals to ‘the mere expression of disease’.
Roger Cooter, for example, has dismissed retrospective diagnosis as ‘inherently condescending’. The discussion about how to approach histories of disease and illness has re-emerged with renewed vigour in recent years with the publication of a slew of disease ‘biographies’. We might usefully think of retrospective diagnosis practice as a broad spectrum, whose ends bear little similarity to each other. At one end of the scale well-funded paleopathology research groups utilise expensive scientific technology to identify pathogens in archaeological remains. High-profile examples of this include the 1976 examination of the mummy of Ramses II by French scientists who wished to prove that the Egyptian pharaoh died from tuberculosis. The question of whether or not the pathogen Yersinia pestis was responsible for the ravages of the Black Death in the medieval and early-modern period almost constitutes a sub-discipline.
Recently, Monica Green has emphasised the value of cross-disciplinary collaborations that take the biological materiality of disease seriously on both global and deep chronological scales. Combining scientific disciplines including paleopathology and genetics with professional history offers a very different kind of disease work than the ‘parlour game’ that imposes various illnesses on historical figures through the interpretation of texts, artefacts, images and commentary. Was King George III’s madness actually porphyria?
Did Nietzsche have syphilis? These kinds of diagnoses have widely been criticised; Caroline Walker Bynum’s discussion in Holy Feast and Holy Fast (1987) regarding whether medieval women can be said to have had ‘anorexia’ remains one of the most convincing explorations of the problems and implications of making such a diagnosis if our aim is to understand a period historically. In particular, Bynum criticised a tendency to assume that we can identify either a ‘secularisation’ or ‘medicalisation’ of behaviour previously regarded as religious, noting that a number of medieval paradigms existed for ‘not eating’. She also noted that the validity of a diagnosis depends on which modern definition of an illness is chosen. If we take examples of retrospective diagnoses as historical artefacts in themselves, however, they can be very revealing. In a recent survey of theories about Jonathan Swift’s ailments over three centuries, for example, Marjorie Lorch notes that while the evidence regarding Swift is inadequate to determine the accuracy of any individual retrospective diagnosis of his ailments, analysing how these diagnoses have changed reveals something of how ‘different signs and symptoms were given status and significance by different writers at different historical periods’. Migraine leaves no physical trace, and offers no scope for bioarchaeological analysis: the idea of Hildegard’s migraine derives from one man’s interpretation of imagery and words.
Hildegard’s case is important because Singer’s diagnosis has persisted beyond the arena of medical hypothesising, and taken on a life of its own as historical evidence in a number of different ways over a long period of time. So can thinking historically about Singer’s diagnosis tell us anything? For a start, it is worth noting that people in the medieval period certainly did have knowledge of, and treatments for, a disorder commonly known as emigranea, a corruption of Galen’s second-century term hemicrania which remains the root of the modern term ‘migraine’. The text of Causae et Curae, generally accepted by recent scholars (contrary to Singer’s view, as we will see below) to be Hildegard of Bingen’s work, albeit a rough draft that she never managed to put into final form, explained emigranea in classical terms, as a disorder that stemmed from melancholy (black bile), and ‘all bad humours present in a person’.
Migraine seizes only half the brain at a time because ‘its strength is such that if it seized the whole head, a person would not be able to endure it’. Treatment involved reducing aloe and myrrh to a fine powder, mixing with wheat flour and poppy oil to make a dough, then covering the whole head. The patient should place a cap over the top and keep on the head for three days and nights. The treatment would sedate the pain and enrich the brain. Another recipe from eleventh-century Chartres recommended the use of peony root frequently stroked over the site of pain, taking a bath with sweet smelling herbs boiled in vinegar or using a cap made with well-boiled hot abrotano (now known as Artemisia).
A thirteenth-century Welsh text recommends a patient to eat a baked or roasted hare’s brain stuffed with rosemary flowers, followed by sleep to treat the ‘migran’. Emigranea was thus understood as a very different disorder to the illness that Hildegard described as her own personal suffering; the best recent translation describes ‘a clouding over of my eyes, and I was so pressed down by the weight of my body that I could not raise myself. So I lay there overwhelmed by my intense pains’. Later she described ‘excruciating airs’ coursing through her whole body, and the ‘marrow in my bones dried up so much it was as if my soul must be released from the body’. It is almost certain that Hildegard would have made no connection between these pains and those of emigranea, not least because in this instance she interpreted her illness as divine punishment.
By 1917, however, when Charles Singer diagnosed Hildegard with migraine, a very different idea of migraine had emerged that did correspond to some extent with Hildegard’s account. Singer’s retrospective diagnosis endowed Hildegard with a migraine devoid of humours, and defined instead by the neurological experience of disordered vision; this was an understanding that had only existed since the 1870s. Singer made his argument based on apparent imagery of migraine aura that he found in the illustrations of the twelfth-century Scivias manuscript, using the texts in which Hildegard described her experience of illness in support. 3. Singer and Hildegard Charles Singer (1876–1960) is best known as the first president of the British Society for the History of Science, founded in 1947. After studying biology, zoology and medicine, Singer chose the latter for his early career, working in Abyssinia, Singapore and Sussex before being appointed as medical officer to the London Cancer Hospital in 1909.
Following his marriage to the medieval historian Dorothy Waley Cohen in 1910, he became increasingly interested in history. His first published articles, on germ theory in Benjamin Marten’s New Theory of Consumptions (1720), early references to tropical diseases and the history of tobacco were received well by his historically inclined peers. Charles Ryell, surgeon to the London Cancer Hospital, thought Singer’s unearthing of Marten’s ‘bygone and forgotten forerunner’ of germ theory to be ‘very enterprising’.
Garrison received Singer’s next articles on ‘Early References to Tropical Diseases’ and the history of tobacco with similar approval: Garrison reported ‘a great deal of interest’ among the officers of the Army Medical School, who felt that the history of medicine was ‘as yet formless and void.’ In 1912, Charles and Dorothy moved to Heidelberg, where he continued his search for predecessors to modern medical concerns and ideas. The librarian at Wiesbaden allowed Charles to consult the illuminated manuscript of Scivias. This was Hildegard of Bingen’s record of her religious visions. From an early age she had experienced waking visions, and a light she described as ‘so great a light that her soul trembled’. In her early forties, ‘the great pressure of my pains’ propelled Hildegard to explain these visions. Through long periods of illness, Hildegard worked for a decade on the text that would become Scivias. In 1148, she received papal approval to write theological works, and subsequently attracted widespread fame as a visionary, preacher and reformer.
Scivias was completed in 1151; it is at once a work of orthodox theology and a remarkable record of Hildegard’s prophetic visions. Since around 1979, the eight-hundredth anniversary of Hildegard’s death, and 1998, when a number of publications commemorated the nine-hundredth year since her birth, Hildegard has attracted sustained attention both by academics, and in popular culture. Her life has been the subject of a feature film, and in Germany a system of alternative holistic healing bears her name. In May 2012, Pope Benedict XVI formally canonised Hildegard before in October of the same year proclaiming her a ‘Doctor of the Church’ in recognition of her teachings, only the fourth woman to receive the honour.
Hildegard would have been, Barbara Newman has suggested, ‘extraordinary in any age’, but for a woman of the twelfth century, her ‘achievements baffle thought’. In addition to recognising the significance of her theological works, historians have granted Hildegard a role in medieval ideas about gender, the human body and nature.
Her oeuvre also includes over seventy liturgical compositions, and a religious drama. Increasingly, Hildegard’s scholars have focused on her medical, as well as religious, ideas. Victoria Sweet, for example, has seen Hildegard as an ‘informant’, who helps us to understand the tenacity of a pre-modern medical model of elements, qualities and humours.
If modern scholars have begun to analyse Hildegard’s medicine on its own terms, Singer’s interest in the second decade of the twentieth century lay in retrospectively using modern medical categories to place Hildegard in a long history of scientific progress. Singer’s attention to Hildegard reflected contemporary historical and antiquarian endeavours to discover, collect, translate and re-publish a plethora of medieval texts, including those attributed to Hildegard. In 1900, Melina Lepinska had described Scivias as ‘one of the most remarkable of Hildegard’s works’. On seeing the extraordinary Wiesbaden manuscript of Scivias for himself, Singer abandoned his work on contagion, and turned his attention to the stars, crenellated shapes, shining lights, fortification figures and concentric circles that characterised the miniatures of Hildegard of Bingen’s religious visions. Singer ‘recognised at once that the figures resembled descriptions by patients of what they had seen during attacks of migraine’ (Figure ). His private letters reveal that he initially shared his ideas with the Swiss physician and historian Arnold Klebs.
‘I was very glad to have the chance to see those beautiful reproductions of the Hildegard manuscripts’, Klebs wrote in the summer of 1913. (Colour online) ‘The Heavenly City’, miniature from Scivias (c.1165), reproduced in Charles Singer (ed.) Studies in the History and Method of Science (Oxford, 1917). And the more I think about it the more I become convinced that you have discovered an eminently interesting subject I do not think anyone in England is tackling medical history with such thoroughness and energy as you do and I have no doubt that in a few years you will have become so expert that we will have to flock to London to learn from you.
Three weeks later, Klebs wrote again: Do not forget that I am anxious to get your Hildegard photographs. I should like to get an illuminated set. I should very much like to show them in America, naturally as coming from you, with your theories on the subject. Perhaps gaining confidence from Klebs’ enthusiasm, Singer presented his ideas about Hildegard in public before the Historical Section of the Royal Society of Medicine in November 1913.
In his talk, he showed the photographs and coloured reproductions of the manuscript illuminations. One member of the audience, Dr R. Hingston Fox, spoke as a personal sufferer from migraine, and agreed that Singer had proved his case. He also suggested to Singer that ‘the blue colours in the pictures were as important as the red, both these hues, as well as others, being characteristic of migrainous spectra’.
William Osler, Regius Professor of Medicine at Oxford, urged Singer to publish his research, and in 1914 invited Singer to take up the Philip Walker Studentship in Pathology at Oxford University. From then on, Singer was enabled to devote virtually all of his time to the history of medicine and science and in June 1914 Dorothea and Charles returned to Wiesbaden to consult the Scivias manuscript again. By late July, travellers’ cheques ceased to be payable in German currency as war with France threatened. The Singers left for Holland, undertaking ‘a most trying journey across the line of German mobilisation we gathered a small party of English and Americans. All of us were nearly penniless and had been forced to abandon our luggage’. Singer’s bags had contained the manuscript of his Hildegard essay. So, after he arrived back in England, Singer rewrote the article from memory.
‘I rather think I improved it’, he later commented. Singer’s re-written article, ‘The Scientific views and visions of Saint Hildegard (1098–1880)’, was finally published in full in 1917, as the first chapter of his edited collection Studies in the History and Method of Science. His theory about the migrainous pathological basis for Hildegard’s religious visions constituted only a four-page coda to a fifty-five-page chapter devoted in the main to explaining Hildegard’s ideas on scientific subjects including the structure of the universe, microcosm and macrocosm, anatomy, physiology, birth, death and the soul. He noted that Hildegard had suffered ill health for much of her life and drew further evidence from Hildegard’s writings about her religious visions, which she experienced ‘neither in sleep, nor in dream, nor in madness (.) But wakeful, alert’. It seemed clear to Singer that Hildegard’s repeated complete recoveries, activity between attacks and long life indicated a functional nervous disorder, an unwieldy category which at this time encompassed neurasthenia, neuralgia and hysteria. Singer diagnosed migraine. ‘In the “more typical” of her visions’, he wrote, ‘the medical reader or the sufferer from migraine will, we think, easily recognise the symptoms of scintillating scotoma’.
To understand where Singer’s ideas about migraine came from, and his references to patients’ descriptions of visual aura we must return to the discussions of scientific men in the middle of the nineteenth century. 4. Migraine and Aura On 30 September 1858, Sir John Herschel (1792–1871), mathematician, astronomer, chemist and photographer, gave a lecture on ‘Sensorial Vision’ to the gathered members of the Leeds Philosophical Society. He told how one morning, at his breakfast table, he had watched a ‘singular shadowy appearance’ at the outside corner of his left field of vision.
The pattern appeared ‘in straight-lined angular forms, very much in general aspect like the drawing of a fortification, with salient and re-entering angles, bastions and ravelins, with some suspicion of faint lines of colour between the dark lines’. Herschel was not alone in publicly recording such a personal experience. In 1865, David Brewster, natural philosopher and inventor of the kaleidoscope, discussed his experiences of ocular spectra, this time in the Philosophical Magazine as a way to contribute to theories about the structure of the optic nerve. Later the same year, the Astronomer Royal, George Biddell Airy, also published an account of his periodic attacks of hemiopsy. In these papers, these men of science did not tend to dwell on other forms of pain or suffering associated with their visual disturbance. Brewster, for example, noted that his attacks ‘were never accompanied either with headache or gastric disturbance’ while Airy, too, observed that ‘in general, I feel no further inconvenience from it’, although his friends found their attacks ‘followed by oppressive head-ache’.
These men were less interested in illness per se than they were in using their personal experiences to advance discussions about optics, vision and light that got to the heart of their beliefs about scientific authority, and indeed the very possibilities of seeing accurately and objectively with the naked eye. Elizabeth Green Musselman has written in detail about the ill health suffered by nineteenth-century men and women of science. She argues that they found meaning in nervous illnesses and failings such as hemiopsy, colour blindness and hallucinations by applying their ideas about refined, well-managed, efficient nervous systems to science and society in general. While these discussions about ‘half-blindness’ contributed to contemporary scientific questions, their public airing also contributed to making these transitory visual attacks socially acceptable, even desirable. In a subsequent essay in the Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London (1870), Hubert Airy, the physician son of the Astronomer Royal, drew together these accounts to propose that all of them (including himself) had experienced a phenomenon that he termed ‘transient teichopsia’.
Hubert did admit to suffering from terrible headache after the ‘blindness’, but did not consider that these visual phenomena were ‘merely’ a disease: such disorders would be ‘hardly deserving of the attention of scientific men’. Rather, these functional disturbances should be regarded as ‘a veritable “Photograph” of a morbid process going on in the brain’, in which case, he thought, ‘their interest and importance cannot be too strongly insisted upon’. Airy accompanied his paper with arguably some of the most beautiful imagery in the history of medicine: a series of sketches illustrating his own experiences of the disturbance across his visual field (Figure ). With ‘changing gleams’ of red, blue, yellow, green and orange, at its height the vision ‘seemed like a fortified town with bastions all round it’. The whole experience lasted half an hour. Despite the variety of words these men employed to discuss hemiopsy, it is important to emphasise that they made virtually no association between their discussions and any of the contemporary terms for migraine (including megrim, hemicrania, sick, nervous or bilious headache).
(Colour online) Plate XXV ‘Stages of Teichopsia’ from Hubert Airy, ‘On a Distinct Form of Transient Hemiopsia’, Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London, 160 (1870). A young Cambridge physician named Edward Liveing was in the audience for Airy’s presentation of his paper to the Royal Society. He was impressed by Airy’s careful observation and minute descriptions, as well as his ‘excellent’ drawings of the spectral appearances. For several years, Liveing had been collecting his own information and patient case notes about a group of ailments including sick, blind and bilious headaches, as well as hemicrania and hemiopsy (Liveing used the term ‘hemiopia’). Liveing believed that these were all closely related. This was not an entirely new argument, but Liveing felt that English physicians needed to better understand these disorders as a family in order to catch up with the more comprehensive knowledge enjoyed by their French and German peers.
Liveing brought these disorders under the umbrella term of megrim, which he explained was part of a larger family of functional disorders that included epilepsy, asthma and angina pectoris, all of which were characterised by paroxysms or fits. Liveing’s book On Megrim, Sick Headache and Some Allied Disorders (1873) is now often considered to be a founding contribution to modern understandings of migraine in the English language. Memorably, Liveing proposed that attacks of megrim in all their manifestations were the result of an event in the body analogous to ‘nerve-storm’: a periodic dispersion of accumulated nervous energy. In the same year, another Cambridge physician, Peter W. Latham, published a second short book of two lectures On Nervous or Sick-Headache. In contrast to Liveing’s nerve-storm theory, Latham explained the cause of migraine’s visual aura as a contraction of the blood vessels of the brain, diminishing the blood supply and disturbing vision, followed by the vessels’ ‘dilatation’ to bring on headache.
Despite their theoretical differences, both books dedicated substantial space to reprinting the discussions that men of science had been having about visual disorders. In so doing, Liveing and Latham took migraine from the largely ignored realms of domestic recipe books, patent remedies and the classified pages of newspapers and infused it with a new authority, relevance and cachet through a firm connection with vision. These discussions were highly gendered and classed. ‘Perhaps in an University town’, Latham commented, ‘it may be more prevalent among males than in other places’. Liveing also explained the disorder as a result of strained intellectual faculties, attacking over-worked students, ‘literary men’ or men who entered ‘the more serious business of life’.
Women were not exempt, but by contrast to men, Liveing’s kind of megrim seemed to attack seamstresses or ‘poor women exhausted from over-suckling’. Throughout the century, medical men had identified lower-class working women, their bodies and nerves broken down by exhaustion, overwork and poor diet, as the main sufferers of migrainous headaches, but megrim’s emerging social visibility and acceptability in the late nineteenth century derived in large part from the central role that new theories about nerves gave to the personal testimony of scientific men, not to the experiences of seamstresses and nurses. In the remaining decades of the nineteenth century physicians from Britain and beyond continued to elaborate their own experiences of migraine in medical journals on both sides of the Atlantic. The most important aspect of these discussions for understanding the background to Singer’s diagnosis of Hildegard’s migraine is that Liveing and Latham also both prominently reproduced Hubert Airy’s diagrams in their studies. Liveing included the image as a double-page pull-out, in full colour, between the index and an analytical table of cases at the end of On Megrim. Latham reproduced it in black and white as the frontispiece to his book. By using Airy’s image in key position in their books, the two physicians transformed Airy’s undeniably beautiful, and instantly recognisable, analysis of his personal experience into a standard bearer for the authentic representation of migraine experience, irrespective of theoretical standpoint.
‘From an occasional and relatively unimportant curiosity’, Mervyn Eadie has observed, migraine with visual aura had become ‘a significant clinical entity in the medicine of English-speaking countries’. In 1895, Sir William Gowers gave the prestigious Bowman lecture to the British Ophthalmological Society in London on the topic of ‘Subjective Visual Sensations’. He commented on the ‘elaborateness and precision’ of Airy’s drawings. Because Airy made notes at the time, and drew his observations ‘with purposed care’, Gowers declared that they held ‘very great weight’ as scientific records.
Thus, by the end of the nineteenth century, Airy’s images had become an example of what Lorraine Daston and Peter Galison have termed a ‘working object’ for migraine: a standardised exemplar that taught practitioners ‘what is worth looking at, how it looks and perhaps most importantly how it should be looked at’. When, two decades later, Charles Singer diagnosed Hildegard’s migraine by comparing the manuscript images in Scivias to descriptions produced by migraine patients, he could only have been thinking of these famous, oft-reproduced (Airy’s image was even reproduced by Jean-Martin Charcot) and instantly recognisable migraine motifs: although other images of migraine had existed, they had been dismissed, and fallen to the wayside in this new formulation of migraine as a disorder experienced by eminent ‘men of science’, and epitomised by Airy’s image. Bolstering Singer’s apparently straightforward recognition of migraine aura in Hildegard’s illuminations, therefore, was a very specific and recent articulation of migraine as a highly gendered disorder associated most strongly with genius, scientific vision and the intensity of male intellectual work. Singer’s diagnosis retrospectively endowed the abbess with a disorder that had become accepted in late-Victorian expectations of the physical and mental constitution of a ‘scientist’. Using his medical knowledge to render the unusual patterns in Hildegard’s religious imagery as the manifestations of a neurological disorder was important because it enabled Singer to sideline Hildegard’s theology and replace it with ‘science’ as the basis for her philosophy of the world. Then, Singer could fit Hildegard into his larger story of scientific progress from the superstitious darkness of the Middle Ages to the light and reason of modern science.
Singer was by no means the only scholar creating medieval ‘scientists’ through such a secularising treatment. Amanda Power has explored how late nineteenth-century scholars also resurrected the reputation of Roger Bacon, for example, by presenting him ‘not so much as a man, but as a “stage” in a long, triumphant scientific history’ which ‘edited out’ the Christian faith intrinsic to Bacon’s work. From his earliest forays into historical research, Singer had been attempting to formulate a meaningful role for the teaching of history for understanding the very nature of medicine and science.
In 1913, Singer had likened the progress of scientific knowledge ‘to the erection of a great building in which no part of the general structure can go far without due attention being given to the other parts’. Mayer has argued, in the aftermath of the First World War Singer would come to see the history of science as an international exercise in scientific humanism, the value of which ‘lay in addressing an age that experimented both with rampant scientific and technological progress and with democracy’. Singer was of a generation of science historians whose knowledge of experimental science was crucial for establishing their vision of history, and their belief in their authority to impart that vision. For Singer, Hildegard was a key piece in this puzzle.
Compared with the ‘dark degradation’ of her contemporaries, he argued that Hildegard was ‘feeling her way to rational explanation of the world’. His twentieth-century readers needed simply ‘to get past the bizarre and visionary form’ into which she cast her theory of the essential similarity of macrocosm and microcosm to find a ‘systematic and skilful presentment’ of a scientific philosophy characterised not by religion, but by common sense, which gave meaning to the facts of nature. Singer had definite views about which of her attributed works Hildegard was actually responsible for. For example, he began his article by rejecting recent claims (that he had elsewhere previously dismissed as a ‘large and tedious literature’) that she was the author of the work known as Causae et Curae. Singer believed that the manuscript of Causae et Curae was ‘ill-written’ and its association with Hildegard was therefore ‘spurious’. ‘Nothing could be more unlike the ecstatic but well-ordered and systematic work of the phrophetess of Bingen than the prosy disorder’ of the ‘scrappy paragraphs’ of Causae et Curae, he wrote. Singer knew that this argument put him in the minority at the time, but the position was crucial for his own construction of Hildegard’s persona; although he agreed that the content of Causae et Curae was definitely scientific ‘in character’, admitting her authorship would detract from the high quality of the science to be found (paradoxically) in her theological works, particularly Scivias.
It is also distinctly possible that Singer recognised that Causae et Curae would undermine his argument in a second way, by providing a medieval definition of migraine that bore no relation to the illnesses Hildegard had experienced. In dealing with Hildegard, Singer thus made three manoeuvres: he diagnosed Hildegard’s religious visions as being migrainous in origin; he sidelined her religion; and he rejected her authorship of ‘unscientific’ works.
Together, these moves all contributed to Singer’s representation of Hildegard as a scientist. In the years he had been working on Hildegard, Singer had developed a firm belief in the early chronology of scientific development, and in science itself as the ‘making of knowledge’. The Middle Ages had witnessed slow decline from ‘the intellectual efficiency of classical antiquity’, reaching ‘the point of lowest degradation of the human intellect’ in the tenth century. From then on, science enjoyed a slow ascent, before a considerable extension of natural knowledge in the thirteenth and fourteenth centuries. Hildegard advanced a coherent philosophy at a critical point in this chronology.
Singer insisted on the need to approach history scientifically, to ‘interpret the past in the light of present knowledge’, which was exactly what he had done in diagnosing Hildegard’s migraine. Singer published a second version of the Hildegard essay in 1928, this time in a collection of essays that laid out his own fully formed theory of the history of scientific progress. From Magic to Science represented his attempt to trace the collapse of ancient science ‘into the swamp of magic’ and the first attempts to recover ‘from that hideous slough’. Singer reiterated that Hildegard’s work was ‘in fact, Science, and with her we have left the Dark Ages and the Dawn has begun’.
He acknowledged that his original essay on Hildegard had aroused criticism from his contemporaries but noted that their complaints had focused on disagreeing with his rejection of Hildegard’s authorship of Causae et Curae, not on his application of medical theory to account for ‘the pathological basis’ of the visions in Scivias. This had ‘been generally accepted by those with any knowledge’ of migraine.
He all but cut the contested section about Causae et Curae from the revised article (a point to which we will return later), but reinforced the argument about migraine; the 1928 version of the article included new captions for the coloured plates which pointed out the migrainous features of the imagery to the lay reader. Diagnosing migraine provided a way for Singer to make Hildegard into a scientist, but in the years following others identified with her as a sufferer. In 1932, for example, R.H. Elliott reported that when he had shown Hildegard of Bingen’s illustrations to several of his patients in consultations, they had recognised features of their own migraine attacks. Demonstrating a more positive view of religion than Singer, Elliott noted that a ‘richness’ of migraine symptoms was ‘more often observed in clever intellectual people endowed with the creative type of mind’, and went on to diagnose Moses, Jeremiah, Ezekiel and Daniel, Paul of Tarsus, St John the Divine and Zoroaster as migraine sufferers.
Elliott’s casual diagnosis of a swathe of biblical and religious figures as migraineurs might seem far-fetched, but it illuminates two points. First, it shows the extent to which the idea of migraine as a disorder associated with creativity, intellect and visual disturbance had gained ground since Liveing’s work in the 1870s. In this formulation other kinds of migraine had receded from view, particularly the older vernacular meanings implied by the word megrim, which incorporated the key symptoms of sickness and headache. Second, Elliott’s discussion of his patients reinforced Dr Hingston Fox’s reaction in 1913 to Singer’s original proposal that Hildegard suffered from migraine: these apparent representations of illness experience seemed to speak across the centuries: history became part of Elliott’s clinical encounter. Beyond Singer’s schema for the history of science, Hildegard had become a sufferer of a timeless disorder. 5. Oliver Sacks Notwithstanding Elliott’s paper, however, and despite being reprinted in 1928 and 1958, Singer’s ideas about Hildegard’s migraine attracted relatively little attention during the first half of the twentieth century.
Physicians interested in functional nervous disorders turned to examining the physical and emotional effects of the 1914–18 war, and ideas about migraine fragmented as researchers suggested roles for pituitary swelling, brain swelling, allergies, endocrine organs and psychological factors. In 1933, Critchley and Ferguson summed up the lack of direction; migraine had become ‘the happy hunting ground of the theorist attacked by representatives of all branches of medicine’. From the 1940s, the influence of the American neurologist Harold Wolff revived vascular theories as a dominant explanation for migraine mechanisms. In the late 1960s, a young neurologist, Oliver Sacks, was inspired to write a new book on migraine after working in a migraine clinic and reading Liveing’s On Megrim. Sacks had also been entirely convinced by Singer’s argument, agreeing that the Scivias images were ‘indisputably migrainous’.
Sacks went further than Singer, and reduced the abbess’ allegorical interpretation of her ecstatic inspiration entirely to physiological process: Hildegard had experienced ‘a shower of phosphenes in transit across the visual field, their passage being succeeded by a negative scotoma’. Sacks’ book, published in 1970, was designed for a general readership and quickly became a seminal account of the history, experience and state of medical knowledge about migraine. Through many editions, revised and expanded in 1985 and again in 1990, it has attracted millions of readers since its first publication. There are two ways to understand how Hildegard performed an important function in Sacks’ work. First, is the treatment of Hildegard’s migraine in the text.
In a similar way to how Singer had organised his article, Sacks initially discussed Hildegard’s migraine almost as a coda to the main scientific discussion around migraine aura. Sacks made no particularly grand historical claim for the importance of Hildegard’s migraine; relegated to an appendix, at first glance the section seems little more than of incidental interest. However, the discussion of Hildegard was placed at the end of Sacks’ ‘largest, strangest’ chapter, in which he argued that although aura lay at the very heart of migraine, nobody had given it sufficient attention since Liveing.
Sacks’ emphasis on migraine aura in 1970 was significant; during the 1950s and 1960s Harold Wolff’s experimental research had firmly established a vascular theory of cranial vessel dilation as the primary explanation for the pathogenesis of migraine. Sacks did not dismiss the importance of vascular changes as explaining the cause of migraine headaches, but argued that they did ‘nothing to explain the origin of migraine attacks’. Sacks’ championing of Hildegard’s migraine thus used history to reinforce a disciplinary statement about the primacy of neurological models for understanding migraine, a question that continues to provoke hostile exchanges today. Sacks presented Hildegard’s migraine in a second way: a black and white line drawing based on the Scivias miniature ‘Vision of the Heavenly City’ has provided the book’s frontispiece for every edition. The permanency of this image is a striking contrast to the constantly updated images and changing titles that have graced Migraine’s covers. The caption accompanying the frontispiece unambiguously tells readers that the figure is ‘a reconstruction from several versions of migrainous origin’.
The text within the book regarding Hildegard has also remained unchanged through the revisions and updates to Migraine. The preface to the 1992 edition opens by stating that the chief features of migraine – its phenomena, and how these are experienced by the patient, its mode of occurrence, the triggers that may provoke it, the general ways in which one may live with it or combat it – none of these has changed in 2000 years. Such a bold statement needs anchoring and Hildegard implicitly acts as such a grounding figure.
Her unchanging migraine legitimates Singer’s neurological medical model for migraine in two millennia of history. At this point, Sally Shuttleworth’s analysis of the growth of child psychology in the late nineteenth century provides a useful parallel.
Shuttleworth recounts the example of an insane baby with enough strength to require restraint by four people, first reported in 1746. In the late nineteenth century a number of medical commentators including the influential psychiatrists James Crichton Browne and Henry Maudsley cited the story with ‘utter credulity’ to insist that children could suffer from insanity. Shuttleworth argues that medical writers have often used such ‘clinical legends’ anachronistically and unproblematically for their own ends.
Once transformed into ‘cases’ by scientific authority, such historical stories take on textual lives of their own as they are repeated over decades. Sacks’ use of Hildegard’s migraine as history is a good example of Shuttleworth’s argument but it also illustrates the paradox that such cases gain authority precisely by becoming increasingly detached from the disciplinary contexts and burdens of proof that supported their elucidation in the first place.
7. Conclusion: Finding Meaning In 2001, two Dutch physicians contributed an editorial comment to the leading headache journal Cephalalgia. Basing their comments on the visual appearance of some of Pablo Picasso’s artwork, they proposed that the artist had been a migraine sufferer. A decade later they admitted, with embarrassment, that ‘our suggestion that Picasso could have suffered from migraine auras without headache was, at that time, not based on research of biographies, letters or memoirs of Picasso or one of his contemporaries’. In the era of global instant media, their theory had spread, and their retraction was too late: a casual diagnosis released by medical ‘experts’ into the public realm had ensured that Picasso joined Hildegard as a famous sufferer of migraine. Does their absence of proof matter? In a recent memoir of living with migraine, Andrew Levy suggests that the reality of such a retrospective diagnosis is, in fact, irrelevant. For Levy, what matters is that whatever their particular muses were, women and men like Hildegard and Picasso, like Woolf and Darwin, all went down the same deep well that the migraine sufferer reaches their cases, taken together, tell us that what we call mystic vision, or creative inspiration, may be vastly more promiscuous and accessible than we generally allow, and that illness may be a gate swung wide open.
For Levy, the importance of people like Hildegard and Picasso is their ability to translate the brain’s ‘elemental language’ into a meaningful form for people who recognise something of themselves in the story. In this context, the significance of these visionary experiences relates to positive creative possibilities that are removed from a need to believe in divine revelation, or connotations of negative pathology. From Charles Singer’s first presentations of his ideas about Hildegard in 1913, sufferers have recognised the Scivias illustrations as reflecting their own experiences of visual disturbance connected with migraine. One recent example of this meaning is on the internet, where contributors to forums discussed whether Hildegard would make a good patron saint of migraine.
As one contributor comments: ‘I’m sure we can use all the saints we can get. I don’t think we found an “official” migraine saint. I didn’t check the archives but I think some of us just decided that Hildegard would be a good choice’. Whatever complicated historical contexts lie behind the life of Hildegard’s diagnosis, her continued popularity illustrates the problem with rejecting retrospective diagnosis outright. If we reject Singer’s diagnosis outright, we deny the real meaning that people have derived from recognising something of their own experiences in historical traces. On the other hand, it is likely that the narrow definition of migraine that the Hildegard imagery represents (a neurologically privileged definition that derived from the nineteenth century, and was revived in part by Oliver Sacks nearly a century later), excludes a large proportion of migraine sufferers who do not see their own experiences in these images, or who do not find in migraine an opportunity to release their creativity.
How do we write histories that can take account of chronicity, nausea, periodicity and pain, rather than just visual disturbance? Hildegard’s migraine shows the importance of paying attention to hidden assumptions that may be reproduced, or agendas served, however unwittingly, by reproducing out of context retrospective claims about the past. Historians need to examine the historical contexts that give rise to retrospective diagnoses, and to be aware that meanings or kinds of evidence may be silenced in the process. These diagnoses can take on a life of their own, and come to serve new purposes that we might later come to regret. The problem with retrospective diagnosis might not lie in its failure to respect the past, but the impossibility of predicting its future, although this, of course, could be said of any historical project.